In this thought-provoking paper, Pava defends the claim that there is a unique Jewish business ethic. In so doing, Pava sets himself apart from those like Kant and Mill who defend the universal character of ethical imperatives. In other words, Pava proposes that there is a business ethics to be found within the texts of Judaism that cannot be reduced to the ethical systems with which we are familiar. To substantiate this claim, Pava argues that Jewish business ethics displays the following features:
1. God as the Ultimate Source of Value:
2. The Centrality of Community:
Unlike other ethical theories, a Jewish ethic is concerned with the community as well the individual; in seeking the morally correct action we are asked to answer the following question, “What does God command us to do?” As such, the communal implications of individual action are taken into account when deciding which behaviours to proscribe. Pava then quotes three principles central to Jewish business ethics which are concerned with “promoting the creation, maintenance, and enhancement of community”: (i) the financial needs of one’s family and community take precedence over the needs of strangers; (ii) we force people to help out others when doing so will come at no cost to themselves (kofin al midat S’dom/one is compelled not to act in the manner of Sodom); (iii) going beyond the letter of the law (lifnim mishurat hadin). Pava quotes a number of interesting scenarios in business where the application of these principles demonstrate a nuanced and commendable business ethic.
3. Individual and Communal Transformation:
The final element of Jewish business ethics is its goal of transforming the individual character which in turn will lead to communal transformation or upliftment: “A living community committed to the ideal of ethical improvement at the level of the individual cannot for long ignore the call for ethical improvement in its powerful organizations and institutions.”
In spite of Pava’s case for there being a business ethic unique to Judaism, a number of concerns come to mind. Firstly, it is unclear how we are to interpret Pava’s claim. There is at least one sense in which it seems obvious that there is a unique Jewish business ethics; that is, given that only Jews are obligated to follow the numerous laws found in Choshen Mishpat (the section of Jewish law relating to commerce), it is obvious that within Judaism there is a unique business ethic. Perhaps, then, Pava has in mind a different kind of “uniqueness,” for instance the claim that the content of Jewish business ethics is unique. But it would be hard to motivate such a “uniqueness” claim based on the content of the three principles he identifies as central to a Jewish business ethic since “secular” systems of ethics can and do incorporate those principles. And if Pava’s claim boils down to Judaism offering a unique combination of those principles, then it remains to be seen if they can cohere within one system, a point which Pava leaves undefended.
Secondly, it is not clear to me that the de facto position within Judaism is that morality depends on God’s will; in other words, there is a strong case to be made for denying that the horn of the Euthyphro problem favoured by Pava captures the Jewish position. (I refer the reader to Michael Harris’s book Divine Command Ethics for further reading on this point.) I don’t want to dwell on this point here since it will be the topic of a forthcoming symposium on this site. However, if the following question does not take us too deeply into the topic of the relationship between religion and ethics, I wouldn’t mind hearing more about the thinking behind this claim since it seems to me, despite what Pava writes in this piece, that he is incorrect when he claims “Ethics, in the final analysis, is not like algebra or physics.”
A third worry, and one which is connected to my first point, is the relevance of the Jewish laws governing business for the non-Jewish world. If, as I claimed earlier, Judaism does indeed contain a unique business ethic, it is not clear to me what relevance this would have for the world of ethics in general. Pava brings test cases in his paper that seem to indicate that Jewish business ethics reaches the right result in those cases. But the “right result,” if there is such a thing, pertains to the world of the beis din (the Jewish court of law) and seems to have no relevance to those outside of its domain. Perhaps, then, Pava is making the stronger claim that Jewish business ethics is a model for all business ethics. This would be a very interesting claim indeed and one I would like to hear more about.
Quick question:
ReplyDeleteDoes anyone know if the principle "kofin al midat s'dom" is a general ethical principle in Judaism or is it one that applies to the domain of the commercial only?
Dani wrote;
ReplyDelete"Pava claims that an action is moral in virtue of being commanded by God. Pava provides a reading of the Binding of Isaac (the akeidah) that supports this claim. Abraham was bound to sacrifice his son, so claims Pava, because God commanded him as there is no higher ethic than the will of God: “If Abraham believes in God, he has no choice. God is the source of his ethical obligation. Whatever God commands, man must obey. No matter how extreme, no matter how radical the sacrifice, Abraham must choose God.” ...
Perhaps, then, Pava is making the stronger claim that Jewish business ethics is a model for all business ethics."
If it is rightly reasoned that God is the source of ethical obligation and man must choose God, then this must be the ethics model for all ethics. The problem comes when the base premise is rejected and thus the model is rejected. It is not reasonable to expect the model to be accepted without the base premise being first accepted.
Dallas Bell
Dallas,
ReplyDeleteI would be interested to hear what you think of the following two scenarios.
Scenario 1:
Suppose morality is to be defined as that which is in accordance with God's will. Suppose further that God only revealed himself to a particular group A. In this scenario is it open to the proponent of divine command ethics to claim that those in group A must follow one ethical system, namely the content of God's revelation to that group, and that the content of that revelation is irrelevant to all those outside of A since if God would have wanted everyone to be bound to the content of the revelation to A God would not have limited the revelation to group A alone?
Scenario 2:
Suppose morality is to be defined as that which is in accordance with God's will. Suppose further that God only revealed himself to several groups A, B, C and that the content of each revelation is different. In this scenario is it open to the proponent of divine command ethics to claim that the content of moral system A is irrelevant to those in B and/or C (where irrelevance is to be defined as "not being bound by")?
Dani, what you seem to be describing in both scenarios is a sub-game equilibrium of mankind efficiency within God's equilibrium of His perfect plan/will. With that set, scenario 1 can be examined for the proposed truth that God's revelation (in this case business ethics) is only relevant to the revealed group A then that revelation would not be efficient/work for other groups. So does it work when employed by all groups that believe (keeping the base premise of the Divine before accepting His ethical behavioral economics model)? Given the opening set, scenario 2 can have its proposed truth examined by analysis of groups A-C having different Divine revelation(s) which complement each other (would seem to be in line with the omniscient Creator) or contradicting each other (not in line with an omniscient Creator). Meaning if the latter is so then the revelation was not logically Divine, due to being at odds with its own self. Thusly, both of your scenarios can get at the (Pava) inference that the Divine and most efficient overall model is for all that believe/accept it.
ReplyDeleteDallas Bell
There is at least one example where Kofin al midat sedom likely applies to family law, see Yevamot 11b.
ReplyDelete-Mattan Erder
Thanks for the reference Mattan
ReplyDeleteDallas, I don;t quite follow your point. Might it be possible to express it in another way, perhaps one with less jargon? i.e. I don't know what "sub-game equilibrium of mankind efficiency" means. Thanks
Dani writes: "express...with less jargon?"
ReplyDeleteI will give it a shot.
"...what you seem to be describing in both scenarios is a sub-game equilibrium of mankind efficiency within God's equilibrium of His perfect plan/will."
--Another way to say this could be that all of mankind and his behavioral parameters is a sort of system designed perfectly by the Creator (some might call that state a equilibrium). Within that system are interactions among the groups/agents/players, if you will, described in your scenarios (sub-games that are striving to be in a equilibrium state).
"With that set, scenario 1 can be examined for the proposed truth that God's revelation (in this case business ethics) is only relevant to the revealed group A then that revelation would not be efficient/work for other groups."
--All the behavioral interactions can be expressed as a set. Scenario 1 can be analyzed for its, business ethics, truth (God's true revelation) by checking the efficiency of the proposal that only group A has revelation which would not be efficient with other non-A groups.
"So does it work when employed by all groups that believe (keeping the base premise of the Divine before accepting His ethical behavioral economics model)?"
--The validity of scenario 1 can be observed by determining if non-A groups also experience efficiency when employing the A model.
"Given the opening set, scenario 2 can have its proposed truth examined by analysis of groups A-C having different Divine revelation(s) which complement each other (would seem to be in line with the omniscient Creator) or contradicting each other (not in line with an omniscient Creator). Meaning if the latter is so then the revelation was not logically Divine, due to being at odds with its own self."
--As with scenario 1, scenario 2 can be analyzed. If groups A, B, C, etc. have been given different revelation they either compliment each other to some degree (interpolate behaviors based on the unique revelation) and are efficient -or- they contradict each other. If they contradict each other this would seem to not be Divine revelation of harmony.
"Thusly, both of your scenarios can get at the (Pava) inference that the Divine and most efficient overall model is for all that believe/accept it."
--It is suggested that your scenarios provide the dialectical tool to determine whether the A-model is good for even non-A groups.
There are, of course, further implications of whether groups are dynamic (may have members of the groups leave one group to join another group) or static (members cannot leave their group). In other words, if a group A member joins group B or C, and vice versa, does the ethics model cease to exist with that person or not. Also, if different groups have different revelations how does that effect distributive, punitive, rectoral, commutative justice, etc. etc.
Dallas Bell